The notion of a
‘public sphere’, developed in the work of Jürgen Habermas (1974), is an
important touchstone for social theorists of democracy and public life. It has given rise to a critical literature
that engages with the concept of a ‘public sphere’ and seeks to assess its
historical validity and contemporary relevance. This discussion has developed
parallel to wider debates on the public/private distinction, the
interrelationship between the public realm and private life , and the
organization of public and private spaces. The present review will group the literature
in terms of approach and delineate common points of analysis and areas of
contestation, moving onto a detailed analysis of selected texts that can offer
guidance for future research on the contemporary utility of the concept of the ‘public
sphere’.
The
literature on the public sphere and related issues of defining the ‘public’ and
‘private’ can be grouped into several different approaches. Habermas’ (1974)
discussion of the structural transformation of the public sphere is a benchmark
of the field and has heavily influenced the work of Fraser (1992, 1998, 2007) whose idea of ‘counterpublics’ breaks with Habermas’ original conception of the bourgeois public sphere, and it also influenced Calhoun
(1998) on the public sphere and the
democratic potential of the internet.
However, the Habermasian conception of the public sphere is only one approach
to the problem of public life and public order. Parallel to this literature,
Silver’s (1990, p. 1481) analysis of 18th Century social theory
probes the relationship between commercial enterprise and the opening up space for
social bonds of “natural sympathy”. Goheen (1998) engages with the issue of
spatial organization in contemporary cities and the impact this has on public
life. The issue of spatial organization is not systematically dealt with in the
work of Habermas (1974); however it is highlighted both by Calhoun (1998) and
Sennett (1977) as important influence on public life. Sennett (2003) has attempted to provide
clarification of this literature, arguing that contemporary social theory on
the public sphere can be defined by its relationship to Georg Simmel’s The Metropolis and Mental Life, which
advanced the notion that in cities individuals adopt a position of indifference
in response to overstimulation, noting the
impersonality that developed in response to overstimulation and constituted a
“mask of rationality”, Sennett argues that
this transformation of the individual personality by the spatial
organization of public space is crucial to understanding the balance of
contemporary public and private life (Sennett, 2003, p. 380).
Sennett
(2003) argues that Habermas’ conception of the public sphere and related
scholarship can be linked to Simmel’s attempt to find the roots of rationality
in civil society and a second tradition can be discerned that stems from
Simmel which emphasises the performative nature of contemporary public life. Sennett (2003) places his own work in this
tradition, particularly The Fall of Public Man (Sennett, 1977), and highlights the contributions of Erving Goffman's work focused on the self-dramatization
of individual difference and the theatricality of public life. Thus, Goffman’s (1963, 1971) ethnographic
work on social rules and face-to-face interaction is an important benchmark for
discussions of social life and the ‘public’ dimension of all interpersonal
interaction. Breaking from these two
traditions outlined by Sennett (2003), segments of the literature interrogate the
notion of ‘public’ and ‘private’ and the instability of these categories. Hansen’s (1997) analysis of women’s lives in
19th century America, demonstrates that the conception of public and
domestic spheres is not borne out by the evidence of women’s lives that are
difficult to categorize in the dichotomous terms of public and private. Weintaub
(1997) argued that the conceptual language of ‘public’ and ‘private’ can often
become quite confused and delineated four major organizing principles of the
‘public/private’ distinction. The literature on the public sphere and related
issues has been grouped; the first section of the literature grouped around
Habermas (1974), the second grouped around Sennett (1977, 2003) and Goffman
(1963, 1972) and a third that interrogate the distinction between private and
public (Weintaub 1997, Hansen,
1997). The detailed analyses of
selected text draw on these three categories.
Habermas’ (1974,
p. 49) conceptualization of the ‘public sphere’ concerned “a realm of our
social life in which something approaching public opinion can be formed”, constituting
an intermediate zone between society and the state. Therefore, Habermas (1974,
p. 49) argues, a “portion of the public sphere comes into being in every
conversation in which private individuals assemble to form a public body”. The historical emergence of the public sphere
is linked to the rise of the bourgeoisie and the struggle against monarchical
absolutism that presented power before the people and reserved deliberative
functions within its own apparatus.
Habermas (1974) linked the proliferation of political clubs, societies
and journals in the 18th century with the burgeoning public sphere. In his analysis of 18th century
social theory, Silver (1990), explores the conception of friendships put forward
by members of the Scottish Enlightenment. In their view, commercial
relationship provided the basis for friendships of “natural sympathy” (Silver,
1990, p. 1480). This parallels Habermas’
notion that the public sphere was constituted by ‘private individuals’ outside
of monarchical authority, in a similar way, friendship was removed from bonds
of feudal obligation. However, the
importance of this a basis for ‘public life’ can be questioned – particularly
from the viewpoints of Sennett (1997) and Goffman (1971, 1963).
Fraser (1992,
p. 109) argued that Habermas’ conception of the public sphere, while deeply
flawed in many respects, is crucial for understanding the “limits of democracy
in late-capitalist societies”. Fraser
(1992, 116) criticizes Habermas’ notion of the public sphere as a unitary institution of bourgeois society
and develops the notion of subaltern “counterpublics” that are discursive zones
in which non-elites form opinions on aspects of social life. These ‘counterpublics” can be linked in with Calhoun's (1998) discussion of social enclaves and the internet, which have a
strong sense of community but break with Habermas’ unitary concept of the
public sphere. With the advent of the
internet, Habermas saw the potential for a new inclusive public sphere,
however, as Calhoun (1998) has noted, the internet is controlled by many of the
same interests that mediate non-internet based forms of communication.
Sennett
(1997, 2003) self-consciously defined his work on the contradistinction to the
tradition of scholarship emblematic of Habermas’ work on the public sphere. To exemplify this, Sennett (2003) outlines
the different approaches taken to the analysis of 18th century
coffee houses. During the 18th
century, coffee house were sites of social interaction and Habermas emphasised
their importance for the communication of information among private individual in
a public body, sites for the circulation
of newspapers and journals, while Sennett emphasised the performance of public roles and the subtle cues that are
required to have your information accepted (Sennett, 2003). This difference of emphasise can be
reconciled, however, Sennett (1977, p. 3) postulated the ‘fall of public man’
were “public life has also become a matter of formal obligation. Most
citizens approach their dealing with the state in a spirit of resigned
acquiescence” during the period of which Habermas described the emergence of a
public sphere.
Goffman’s
(1971) analysis of public life proceeded from ethnographic studies of
face-to-face interaction and therefore can be conceptualized as a micro-foundation
for macro-sociological concepts such as the public sphere. However, Goffman’s (1963, 1971) conception of
‘public life’ and ‘public order’ is much broader than the definition of
‘public’ employed in the Habermasian conception of the public sphere. Social interaction, two individuals passing
each other on the street, is a public act.
For Goffman (1971, p. 40), public order is founded on individual’s
“management of co-presence” according to a series of “ground rules” that people
preform on a daily basis. Thus, as Weintaub
(1997, p. 2) describes it, Goffman’s Relations in Public differentiates between the public world of “sociability” and the
“privacy of the individual self”.
Sennett (1977) argues that the public realm has been devalued in an era
in which personality is directed inwardly towards concerns of selfhood. The
boundary between public and private, and the relative weight of each in
contemporary society is highly contentious.
Weintaub (1997,
p. 7) conceptualized four paradigms that distinguish between public and private
distinction; 1) the liberal-economic model, 2) republican-virtue, 3)
dramaturgical and 4) feminist distinction between the family and the wider
political and economic sphere. Weintaub (1997) demonstrated that the
private/public distinction, while analytically useful, is socially constructed
by historical actors on an ideological and discursive field and therefore
difficult to sustain on an empirical level.
By problematizing this distinction,
Weintaub’s (1997) analysis of the social construction of the
‘public’/’private’ distinction is important to formulations of research
questions on the continued relevance of the ‘public’ sphere in contemporary
life.
The literature
on the public sphere and related issues of public/private distinction, the
interrelationship between the public realm and private life, and the
organization of public and private spaces is broad and encompasses varied
interpretations of fundamental categories of analysis. The most pressing issue in contemporary
society and the continued relevance of the public sphere is: to what extend
does the internet provide the basis for a new public sphere? Habermas’ (1974) notion of the public sphere
is foundational, however other important developments in this field may be traced to critical investigations of this concept by
Fraser (1992) and her notion of ‘counterpublics’ and Calhoun’s
(1998) work on the democratic potential of the internet. This literature
highlights that the contemporary ‘public sphere’ cannot be thought of in
unitary terms and that the internet is not effective without independent social
networks. The contrary tradition represented
by Sennett (1977, 2003) and Goffman (1963, 1971) tactfully used can broaden the
range of analysis and the dramaturgical aspects of social interaction in the
public realm. Weintaub (1997) outlined
the various interpretations of the public/private distinction operating in
society, and therefore the contested nature of the division and the conceptual
confusion that surrounds it which any future study of the public sphere would
have to contend. Thus, the wide range
of literature provides a basis from which to ask the question: to what extent
does the internet provide the basis for a new public sphere?
Written by Mathew Toll.
Bibliography.
Calhoun, C.
(1998) “ Community Without Propinquity Revisited:Communications Technology and
The Transformations of the Urban Public Sphere”, Sociological Inquiry, 68,3,pp.373-397
Fraser, N.
(1992) ‚”Rethinking the Public Sphere: A Contribution to the Critique of
Actually Existing Democracy”.‛ Pp. 109-142 in Habermas and the Public Sphere, edited by Calhoun, Craig. Cambridge
(MA)/London: MIT Press.
Fraser, N. (2007) “On the Legitimacy and Efficacy of
Public Opinion in a PostWestphalian World, Transnationalizing the Public
Sphere”, Theory Culture Society, 24:
pp. 7-30.
Fraser, N. (1998)”Sex Lies and the Public Sphere:
Reflections on the confirmation of Clarence Thomas Feminism”, the public and the private, Joan B.
Landes (ed.) Oxford ;New York : Oxford University Press, pp.314-337.
Goffman,E.
(1963)Behaviour in Public Places: Notes
on the Social Organization of Gatherings, Free Press, New York.
Goffman, E.
(1971) Relations in Public: Microstudies
of the public order, Harper and Rowe, New York.
Goheen,Peter(1998)”Public
Space and the Geography of the Modern City”, Progress in
Human Geography, 22:479-496.
Habermas, J.(
1974), “The Public Sphere: An Encyclopaedia Article”, New German Critique, No. 3, pp 49-55.
Hansen, Karen V.
(1997) “Rediscovering the Social Visiting Practices in Antebellum New England”,
in Public and Private in Thought and
Practice: perspectives on a grand dichotomy eds. Weintraub, J. And Kumar,K,
University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp.268-301.
Sennett, R.
(1977) The Fall of Public Man. New
York: Knopf.
Sennett, Richard
(2003) “Reflections on The Public Realm” in (Gary Bridge and Sophie Watson
(eds.) A Companion to the City ,
Blackwell Publishing, Malden MA.
Silver, Allan
(1990) ‚”Friendship in Commercial Society: Eighteenth-Century Social Theory and
Modern Sociology”, The American Journal
of Sociology, Vol. 95, No. 6 (May, 1990), pp. 1474-1504.
Weintraub, Jeff,
(1997) “The Theory and Politics of the Public Private Distinction”, Weintraub,
J. And Kumar, K, (eds.) Public and Private
in Thought and Practice: perspectives on a grand dichotomy, University of
Chicago Press, Chicago, pp.1-42.
No comments:
Post a Comment